home *** CD-ROM | disk | FTP | other *** search
- Newsgroups: sci.physics
- Path: sparky!uunet!psinntp!scylla!daryl
- From: daryl@oracorp.com (Daryl McCullough)
- Subject: Re: hidden variables
- Message-ID: <1993Jan22.141944.7214@oracorp.com>
- Organization: ORA Corporation
- Date: Fri, 22 Jan 1993 14:19:44 GMT
- Lines: 110
-
- paul@mtnmath.UUCP (Paul Budnik) writes:
-
- >> >When we observe the first photon in a test of Bell's inequality we must
- >> >assume that the singlet state *pair* has become *exactly* aligned with the
- >> >polarizer that photon just traversed. It is this assumption that implicitly
- >> >involves collapse.
- >>
- >> I agree. But that assumption is not necessary; all that is necessary
- >> is that the probability of observing photon 1 pass through a polarizer
- >> at angle A *and* of observing photon 2 pass through a polarizer at angle
- >> B is ... [whatever the quantum prediction is].
- >
- >The question is: what are the principles of quantum mechanics necessary
- >to derive that joint probability? If you do not use quantum collapse to
- >generate such an alignment how can you derive the joint probability
- >distribution?
-
- Paul, you will have to tell me what you think would resolve this
- impasse. It is mathematically possible to write down a set of
- standard axioms for quantum mechanics, delete the axiom referring
- to collapse of the wave function, and still derive the predictions
- for joint probability of detection in twin particle experiments.
- The collapse hypothesis in not mathematically necessary.
-
- Perhaps you are saying that there is no way to get the system in
- the appropriate initial condition (a singlet state of the twin
- particles) without the collapse hypothesis?
-
-
- >Keep in mind that before the observation of either photon
- >there is a particular wave function at each site.
-
- No, I don't think that there is. There is a probability distribution
- in phase space, but there is no unambiguous probability distribution
- at each site.
-
- >The probability of observing either photon based on this wave
- >function does not give the correct answer for joint probabilities. The
- >distant wave function has to be changed based on the local observation
- >to get a wave function at the distant site that will produce the
- >correct probabilities.
-
- You can certainly go from a two-particle wavefunction to two
- one-particle wave functions by simply integrating over the unwanted
- coordinates. However, by doing such an integration, you are throwing
- away information, you are averaging over variables that you don't care
- about. Whether or not you view the full wave function as physical,
- there is no absolutely no reason to think of the results after
- averaging to be a physical quantity. Quantum mechanics does not say
- *anything* about one-particle wave functions; they are always simply
- approximations to a full, many-particle wave function.
-
- >We have a singlet state wave function that implies a correlation between
- >some observable in two distant particles. I agree that you can derive
- >the correlations from this principle by simply arguing that since
- >these properties are correlated the observations must have a certain
- >correlation. You can argue that collapse is not needed to reach this
- >conclusion. I think this prediction outside the wave function model
- >is a specious argument. The only model QM supports is the wave function
- >model (or an equivalent formalism) and I think all QM arguments
- >implicitly depend on that model. But all this does not matter
- >because you cannot prove that Bell's inequality
- >will be violated without using collapse.
-
- Paul, I have derived the violation of Bell's inequality myself, and
- I didn't assume collapse---I only assumed the quantum prediction for
- probabilities of observations. (To get the probability of measuring
- observable A to have value a, write the wave function |Psi> as
- a supersition |Psi> = c1 |Psi_a> + c2 |Psi'>, where |Psi_a> is
- an eigenfunction of A with value a, and |Psi'> is orthogonal to
- |Psi_a>. In the EPR experiment, if you let A be the operator that
- returns the pair of spins for the two particles, then the correlations
- that violate Bell's inequality follows.)
-
- >To get that you need more than
- >correlations. It is easy using local processes to construct a system that
- >will violate Bell's inequality as a mathematical relationship. To get
- >a violation of Bell's inequality you must show that there is a space-like
- >separation between when you manipulate some experimental parameter,
- >for example a polarization angle, and when this has an effect on the
- >probability for joint detections.
-
- Bell's inequality is simply a statement about correlations. I think
- what you mean is that the violation of Bell's inequality is only
- surprising in the circumstances you are talking about.
-
- >Strictly speaking you need to have
- >two polarizers that are manipulated and both these manipulations must
- >be space-like separated from the more distant detector to rule out any
- >possibility of a local hidden variables model. To predict this timing
- >relationship requires the assumption that the wave function changes
- >instantaneously when an observation is made. If the wave function changes
- >in a local fashion when an observation is made you will still get the
- >correlations but you will not get a violation of Bell's inequality.
-
- I don't think that you have that completely right. It is impossible
- for the correlations to reproduce the predictions of quantum mechanics
- without violating Bell's inequality. If quantum mechanics were false
- (if your theory that the wave function is a physical quantity that
- propagates at light speed were correct), then you would find that for
- very distant measurements taken close together in time the quantum
- predictions for correlations would be wrong. There is no way to preserve
- the correlations without violating Bell's inequality.
-
- Daryl McCullough
- ORA Corp.
- Ithaca, NY
-
-
-
-