home *** CD-ROM | disk | FTP | other *** search
- Path: sparky!uunet!elroy.jpl.nasa.gov!usc!zaphod.mps.ohio-state.edu!cis.ohio-state.edu!news.sei.cmu.edu!drycas.club.cc.cmu.edu!pitt.edu!sgast
- Newsgroups: talk.abortion
- Subject: Re: t.a. FAQ (part 3 of 3)
- Message-ID: <1291@blue.cis.pitt.edu>
- From: sgast+@pitt.edu (Susan Garvin)
- Date: 1 Jan 93 00:39:47 GMT
- Sender: news+@pitt.edu
- References: <1992Dec31.203102.9788@ncsu.edu> <1285@blue.cis.pitt.edu> <1992Dec31.225226.14301@ncsu.edu>
- Distribution: na
- Organization: University of Pittsburgh
- Lines: 104
-
- In article <1992Dec31.225226.14301@ncsu.edu> dsholtsi@csl36h.csl.ncsu.edu (Doug Holtsinger) writes:
-
- [text deleted in which Rev. Holtsinger altered my words to help
- him pretend that he hasn't deleted a relevant portion from the
- quote]
-
- #No, the decision does not contradict Mark Tushnet's analysis
- #of Roe v. Wade.
-
- You're lying, DODie.
-
-
- ROE v. WADE
- 410 U.S. 113; 93 S. Ct. 705; 35 L. Ed. 2d 147 (1973)
-
- Mr. Justice Blackmun delivered the opinion of the Court, saying in
- part:
- [...]
- On the basis of elements such as these, appellants and some
- amici argue that the woman's right is absolute and that she is en-
- titled to terminate her pregnancy at whatever time, in whatever
- way, and for whatever reason she alone chooses. With this we do
- not agree. Appellants' arguments that Texas either has no valid
- interest at all in regulating the abortion decision, or no inter-
- est strong enough to support any limitation upon the woman's sole
- determination, is unpersuasive. The Court's decisions recognizing
- a right of privacy also acknowledge that some state regulation in
- areas protected by that right is appropriate. As noted above, a
- State may properly assert important interests in safeguarding
- health, in maintaining medical standards, and in protecting poten-
- tial life. At some point in pregnancy, these respective interests
- become sufficiently compelling to sustain regulation of the fac-
- tors that govern the abortion decision. The privacy right in-
- volved, therefore, cannot be said to be absolute. In fact, it is
- not clear to us that the claim asserted by some amici that one has
- unlimited right to do with one's body as one pleases bears a close
- relationship to the right of privacy previously articulated in the
- Court's decisions. The Court has refused to recognize an unlimited
- right of this kind in the past. Jacobson v. Massachusetts (1905)
- (vaccination); Buck v. Bell (1927) (sterilization).
- We therefore conclude that the right of personal privacy in-
- cludes the abortion decision, but that this right is not un-
- qualified and must be considered against {important} state
- interests in regulation.
- Where certain "fundamental rights" are involved, the Court
- has held that regulation limiting these rights may be justified
- only by a "compelling state interest," Kramer v. Union Free School
- District (1969), Shapiro v. Thompson (1969),...and that legisla-
- tive enactments must be narrowly drawn to express only the le-
- gitimate state interests at stake. Griswold v. Connecticut
- (1965)....
- [...]
- X.
-
- In view of all this, we do not agree that, by adopting one theory
- of life, Texas may override the rights of the pregnant woman that
- are at stake. We repeat, however, that the State does have an im-
- portant and legitimate interest in preserving and protecting the
- health of the pregnant woman, whether she be a resident of the
- State or a nonresident who seeks medical consultation and treat-
- ment there, and that it has still ANOTHER important and legitimate
- interest in protecting the potentiality of human life. These in-
- terests are separate and distinct. Each grows in substantiality as
- the woman approaches term and, at a point during pregnancy, each
- becomes "compelling."
- With respect to the State's important and legitimate interest
- in the health of the mother, the compelling point, in light of the
- present medical knowledge, is at approximately the end of the
- first trimester. This is so because of the now established medical
- fact, referred to above...that until the end of the first trimes-
- ter mortality in abortion is less than mortality in normal child-
- birth. It follows that, from and after this point, a State may
- regulate the abortion procedure to the extent that the regulation
- reasonably relates to the preservation and protection of maternal
- health. Examples of permissible state regulation in this area are
- requirements as to the qualifications of the person who is to per-
- form the abortion; as to the licensure of that person; as to the
- facility in which the procedure is to be performed, that is,
- whether it must be a hospital or may be a clinic or some other
- place of less-than-hospital status; as to the licensing of the fa-
- cility; and the like.
- This means, on the other hand, that, for the period of preg-
- nancy prior to this "compelling" point, the attending physician,
- in consultation with his patient, is free to determine, without
- regulation by the State, that in his medical judgment the
- patient's pregnancy should be terminated. If that decision is
- reached, the judgment may be effectuated by an abortion free of
- interference by the State.
- With respect to the State's important and legitimate interest
- in potential life, the "compelling" point is at viability. This is
- so because the fetus then presumably has the capability of mean-
- ingful life outside the mother's womb. State regulation protective
- of fetal life after viability thus has both logical and biological
- justifications. If the State is interested in protecting fetal
- life after viability, it may go so far as to proscribe abortion
- during that period except when it is necessary to preserve the
- life or health of the mother.
-
-
- [Many thanks to Russ Anderson]
-
- Susan
-
-
-