home *** CD-ROM | disk | FTP | other *** search
- Path: sparky!uunet!zaphod.mps.ohio-state.edu!saimiri.primate.wisc.edu!caen!destroyer!ncar!noao!arizona!gudeman
- From: gudeman@cs.arizona.edu (David Gudeman)
- Newsgroups: sci.logic
- Subject: recursive definitions and paradoxes
- Message-ID: <26788@optima.cs.arizona.edu>
- Date: 19 Nov 92 20:16:01 GMT
- Organization: U of Arizona CS Dept, Tucson
- Lines: 211
-
- A "recursive definition" of a name X is a sentence of the form
-
- X := E
-
- where E is an expression that contains X as a free variable. Naively we
- might associate with such definitions the axiom
-
- X := E => X = E
-
- To express what a definition means. (We also need some syntactic rules
- to allow the introduction of definitions so that the same name is not
- used for different purposes.)
-
- Here are some examples of recursive definitions:
-
- (1) x := x + 1
- (2) x := x * 2
- (3) x := 1/x
- (4) x := x * 1
-
- Definition (1) fails to define x because there is no x that satisfies
- the equation. (3) and (4) both fail to define x because there are more
- than one object that satisfy the equation. (2) defines x = 0 because
- that is the unique solution to the equation. When a recursive
- definition is based on an equation that has a unique solution, then it
- is called a well-founded recursion. If the equation has no solution or
- more than one solution, the recursion is said to be ill-founded.
-
- Using (1) and the naive axiom of definition you can prove
-
- x := x + 1
- x = x + 1
- x - x = 1
- 0 = 1
-
- which is a contradiction. The lesson is that before you can use a
- recursive definition in a proof, you must show that it is well-founded.
-
- A recursive set definition might look like this:
-
- S := {x : (x = {} or x = S) and ~(x E x)} (5)
-
- It should be clear that (5) is a recursive definition. It should also
- be clear that there is no S satisfying the equation implied by the
- definition, therefore it is an ill-founded recursive definition.
- Furthermore, there is no need to look further for an ``explanation'' of
- the inconsistency that arises when you assume that the definition
- actually defines something. When you have said that the definition is
- an ill-founded recursive definition you have said all that needs to be
- said.
-
- What I have written up to now is well-known and should be
- uncontroversial. So now lets apply the notions to the theory ZF (or Z,
- for that matter) by adding definitions with the proper syntactic
- restrictions and adding the naive axiom of definition:
-
- X := E -> X = E
-
- to get the theory ZF+ND. (This theory is inconsistent, but let's ignore
- that for now). In ZF+ND you can form the following paradoxical set:
-
- S := {x E {{},S} : ~(x E x)} (6)
-
- Clearly, this is logically equivalent to (5) and so is also a definition
- based on an ill-founded recursion. This is a simplified version of the
- paradox of the library catalogue that lists all catalogues that do not
- list themselves. Curry, in _Foundations of Logic_ dismisses this
- paradox rather sanguinely as a ``pseudo-paradox'', saying that the
- catalog just cannot be constructed. But it is obvious (to me, anyway)
- that this is merely a finite version of Russel's paradox, less artfully
- concealed because the recursion is explicit.
-
- But consider the paradoxical definitions
-
- S := {{},R}
- R := {x E S : ~(x E x)} (8)
-
- where the definition of R has exactly the same form as the definition of
- Russell's paradoxical set (replacing S with the universal set). But
- here, S is a set with only two elements! Given such a clear example of
- Russell's paradox by quantifying over a finite set, I don't see how
- anyone can still claim that Russell's paradox is somehow caused by a
- universal set that is "too big". Size has nothing to do with it, the
- only consideration is how it is defined. Clearly in this example the
- problem is an ill-founded mutual recursion between the two set
- definitions.
-
- Now let us take one more step and consider the theory ZF+ND+U of ZF+ND
- with a universal set axiom:
-
- Forall y. y E U
-
- People knowledgeable in set theory will immediately recognize this as an
- inconsistent theory, because ZF |- ~U. However, the theory ZF+ND is
- already inconsistent, so I haven't done any damage. If the reader will
- bear with me I will solve both of these inconsistencies in one swell
- foop at the end (trust me :-).
-
- Consider
-
- S := {x in U : ~(x E S)}
-
- which is an ill-founded recursive definition. If you replaced the
- second S with another set (that is not defined recursively with S), then
- this definition would not lead to inconsistency, so I hope that everyone
- will agree with me that the "cause" of the inconsistency in the above is
- the ill-founded recursion.
-
- Now consider Russell's paradoxical set
-
- R := {x E U : ~(x E x)}
-
- which is clearly not recursive in the sense I gave above. In other
- words, the name being defined does not occur (syntactically) in the
- expression. Just as clearly though, this R is closely related to the
- one in (8). I claim then, that there is an ill-founded mutual recursion
- going on between this definition and the definition of U. Basically, U
- is defined by quantifying over all y, where R is one of the y.
- Similarly, R is defined as an element of U. Recursion-by-quantifier is
- not included my original definition of recursion, so I will have to
- broaden the definition.
-
- Before I give my new definition of recursion, let me discuss
- impredicativity and explain why I did not use that term to begin with.
- Impredicativity, as I understand it, is the use of a quantifier over a
- domain that is incomplete in some sense. One might say that {x E U :
- ~(x E x)} is impredicative because x quantifies over a set U that
- contains x, and that U is not complete until x is defined. I don't like
- this notion because it seems vague. After all, there is no time for
- mathematical objects, so the phrase "when" must be an analogy for
- something _like_ a period of time, but I have no idea what this
- analogous thing is. (Whatever it is, it is _not_ a stage in the
- iterative hierarchy, because assuming that is equivalent to assuming
- that all sets are defined by the iterative hierarchy --a position that I
- deny.)
-
- Now I could have used the term "impredicative" instead of "recursion"
- since I am forced to generalize either term to make it work. I chose
- recursion in order to avoid giving the impression that I was making
- arguments similar to the various arguments about impredicativity that
- have been made before. But I have not agreed with any of those
- arguments, and I wanted to avoid this confusion. Unfortunately, the
- confusion arose anyway. I hope these comments are enough to straighten
- things out.
-
- Going back to recursion, I want a redefinition of the concept that will
- bring out the similarity in all the inconsistent definitions I have
- proposed. Clearly, S := {x E U : ~(x E x)} does contain a sort of
- circularity in that the variable x quantifies over a set that contains
- S. We can expand the above notation into something like
-
- S := (if x1 E x1 then {} else {x1}) union
- (if x2 E x2 then {} else {x2}) union
- (if x3 E x3 then {} else {x3}) union ...
-
- with one term for each set in U. If we do so (and the sets are
- enumerable) we will find one expression at some finite position i where
- xi = S. There is the recursion. The recursion is not syntactic, but
- there is certainly a circularity in the definition.
-
- So I propose to redefine the notion of a recursive definition to be
- something like "X := E is recursive if E contains a free occurence of
- X or if E contains a bound variable that quantifies over a class that
- include the value that X would denote if it denotes anything". "Would
- denote" obviously requires formalization. Furthermore, this definition
- does not include the possibility of a term F(y) where y quantifies over
- such a range that F(y) = X for some y. So I propose
-
- Definition: a definition X := E is _recursive_ iff there is a proper
- subterm F of E such that X=E => X=F for some legal substitution of the
- bound variables in E.
-
- This does not entirely solve the problem of Russell's paradox because
- that paradox exists without the axiom of definition. So I propose the
- following definition of a recursive term:
-
- Definition: a term E is _recursive_ iff there is a proper subterm F of
- E such that E=F for some legal substitution of the bound variables in E.
-
- Then we can talk about ill-founded recursive terms as well as about
- recursive definitions. The distinction, I think, is not essential.
-
- Notice that I am not claiming that all recursion causes paradox. On the
- contrary, I believe that set theories should allow recursion, and ZF's
- lack of it is one of the reasons I think the theory is inadequate. I
- claim that the problem is caused specifically by _ill-founded_ recursion
- in my sense, namely that the equation implied by the definition does not
- have a unique solution.
-
- And I don't think that there is any mysterous problem about ``defining
- something in terms of itself'' or ``quantifying over something that does
- not yet exist''. There is simply the problem that some equations don't
- have unique solutions. And this problem only tells us that we have to
- be careful what we take to be definitions, it does not tell us that some
- sets are too big to be sets, that self-reference is illegitimate, or
- that recursion is illegitimate.
-
- I propose for discussion the
-
- Axiom of Definition: (X := E /\ Exist! X.X=E) => X = E
-
- where "Exist! x" means "there exists a unique x such that". What if you
- altered ZF to contain this axiom (and introduction of definitions)? In
- the first place, you could immediately prove the existence of all sets
- that are already there. And by adding some of the well-known machinery
- from recursion theory to prove Exist!... you could also talk about a lot
- of self-containing sets. Wouldn't this theory be much more powerful
- than ZF?
- --
- David Gudeman
- gudeman@cs.arizona.edu
-