home *** CD-ROM | disk | FTP | other *** search
- Newsgroups: sci.cryonics
- Path: sparky!uunet!decwrl!parc!merkle
- From: merkle@parc.xerox.com (Ralph Merkle)
- Subject: The Technical Feasibility of Cryonics; Part #2
- Message-ID: <merkle.722466887@manarken>
- Sender: news@parc.xerox.com
- Organization: Xerox PARC
- Date: 22 Nov 92 21:14:47 GMT
- Lines: 876
-
- The Technical Feasibility of Cryonics
-
- PART 2 of 5.
-
- by
-
- Ralph C. Merkle
- Xerox PARC
- 3333 Coyote Hill Road
- Palo Alto, CA 94304
- merkle@xerox.com
-
- A shorter version of this article appeared in:
- Medical Hypotheses (1992) 39, pages 6-16.
-
-
- ----------------------------------------------------------
-
- CRITERIA OF DEATH
-
- "death \'deth\ n [ME deeth, fr. OE death; akin to ON dauthi death,
- deyja to die - more at DIE] 1: a permanent cessation of all vital
- functions : the end of life"
- Webster's New Collegiate Dictionary
-
- Determining when "permanent cessation of all vital functions" has
- occurred is not easy. Historically, premature declarations of death and
- subsequent burial alive have been a major problem. In the seventh
- century, Celsus wrote "... Democritus, a man of well merited celebrity,
- has asserted that there are in reality, no characteristics of death
- sufficently certain for physicians to rely upon."[87, page 166].
-
- Montgomery, reporting on the evacuation of the Fort Randall Cemetery,
- states that nearly two percent of those exhumed were buried alive[87].
-
- "Many people in the nineteenth century, alarmed by the prevalence of
- premature burial, requested, as part of the last offices, that wounds or
- mutilations be made to assure that they would not awaken ... embalming
- received a considerable impetus from the fear of premature burial."[87].
-
- New Criteria
-
- Current criteria of "death" are sufficient to insure that spontaneous
- recovery in the mortuary or later is a rare occurence. When examined
- closely, however, such criteria are simply a codified summary of
- symptoms that have proven resistant to treatment by available
- techniques. Historically, they derive from the fear that the patient
- will spontaneously recover in the morgue or crypt. There is no
- underlying theoretical structure to support them, only a continued
- accumulation of ad hoc procedures supported by empirical evidence. Each
- new medical advance forces a reexamination and possible change of the
- existing ad hoc criteria. The criteria used by the clinician today to
- determine "death" are dramatically different from the criteria used 100
- years ago, and have changed more subtly but no less surely in the last
- decade[ft. 7]. It seems almost inevitable that the criteria used 200
- years from now will differ dramatically from the criteria commonly
- employed today.
-
- These ever shifting criteria for "death" raise an obvious question: is
- there a definition which will not change with advances in technology? A
- definition which does have a theoretical underpinning and is not
- dependent on the technology of the day?
-
- The answer arises from the confluence and synthesis of many lines of
- work, ranging from information theory, neuroscience, physics,
- biochemistry and computer science to the philosophy of the mind and the
- evolving criteria historically used to define death.
-
- When someone has suffered a loss of memory or mental function, we often
- say they "aren't themselves." As the loss becomes more serious and all
- higher mental functions are lost, we begin to use terms like "persistent
- vegetative state." While we will often refrain from declaring such an
- individual "dead," this hesitation does not usually arise because we
- view their present state as "alive" but because there is still hope of
- recovery to a healthy state with memory and personality intact. From a
- physical point of view we believe there is a chance that their memories
- and personalities are still present within the physical structure of the
- brain, even though their behavior does not provide direct evidence for
- this. If we could reliably determine that the physical structures
- encoding memory and personality had in fact been destroyed, then we we
- would abandon hope and declare the person dead.
-
- The Information Theoretic Criterion of Death
-
- Clearly, if we knew the coordinates of each and every atom in a person's
- brain then we would (at least in principle) be in a position to
- determine with absolute finality whether their memories and personality
- had been destroyed in the information theoretic sense, or whether their
- memories and personality were preserved but could not, for some reason,
- be expressed. If such final destruction had taken place, then there
- would be little reason for hope. If such destruction had not taken
- place, then it would in principle be possible for a sufficiently
- advanced technology to restore the person to a fully functional and
- healthy state with their memories and personality intact.
-
- Considerations like this lead to the information theoretic criterion of
- death[ft. 8]. A person is dead according to the information theoretic
- criterion if their memories, personality, hopes, dreams, etc. have been
- destroyed in the information theoretic sense. That is, if the
- structures in the brain that encode memory and personality have been so
- disrupted that it is no longer possible in principle to restore them to
- an appropriate functional state then the person is dead. If the
- structures that encode memory and personality are sufficiently intact
- that inference of the memory and personality are feasible in principle,
- and therefore restoration to an appropriate functional state is likewise
- feasible in principle, then the person is not dead.
-
- A simple example from computer science is in order. If a computer is
- fully functional, then its memory and "personality" are completely
- intact. If we took an axe to the CPU, then the computer would no longer
- be functional. However, its memory and "personality" would still be
- present on disk, and once we repaired the CPU we could fully restore the
- computer[ft. 9].
-
- In a similar fashion, as long as the structures that encode the memory
- and personality of a human being have not been irretrievably "erased"
- (to use computer jargon) then restoration to a fully functional state
- with memory and personality intact is in principle feasible. Any
- technology independent definition of "death" should conclude that such a
- person is not dead, for a sufficiently advanced technology could restore
- the person to a healthy state.
-
- On the flip side of the coin, if the structures encoding memory and
- personality have suffered sufficient damage to obliterate them beyond
- recognition, then death by the information theoretic criterion has
- occurred. An effective method of insuring such destruction is to burn
- the structure and stir the ashes. This is commonly employed to insure
- the destruction of classified documents. Under the name of "cremation"
- it is also employed on human beings and is sufficient to insure that
- death by the information theoretic criterion takes place.
-
- More Exotic Approaches
-
- It is not obvious that the preservation of life requires the physical
- repair or even the preservation of the brain[11,12]. Although the brain
- is made of neurons, synapses, protoplasm, DNA and the like; most modern
- philosophers of consciousness view these details as no more significant
- than hair color or clothing style. Three samples follow.
-
- The ethicist and prolific author Robert Veatch said, in "Death, Dying,
- and the Biological Revolution", "An 'artificial brain' is not possible
- at present, but a walking, talking, thinking individual who had one
- would certainly be considered living."[15, page 23].
-
- The noted philosopher of consciousness Paul Churchland said, in "Matter
- and Consciousness," "If machines do come to simulate all of our internal
- cognitive activities, to the last computational detail, to deny them the
- status of genuine persons would be nothing but a new form of
- racism."[12, page 120].
-
- Hans Moravec, renowned roboticist and Director of the Mobile Robot Lab
- at Carnegie Mellon said, "Body-identity assumes that a person is defined
- by the stuff of which a human body is made. Only by maintaining
- continuity of body stuff can we preserve an individual person.
- Pattern-identity, conversely, defines the essence of a person, say
- myself, as the pattern and the process going on in my head and body, not
- the machinery supporting that process. If the process is preserved, I
- am preserved. The rest is mere jelly."[50, page 117].
-
- We'll Use the Conservative Approach
-
- Restoration of the existing structure will be more difficult than
- building an artifical brain (particularly if the restoration is down to
- the molecular level). Despite this, we will examine the technically more
- exacting problem of restoration because it is more generally acceptable.
- Most people accept the idea that restoring the brain to a healthy state
- in a healthy body is a desirable objective. A range of increasingly
- less restrictive objectives (as described) are possible. To the extent
- that more relaxed criteria are acceptable, the technical problems are
- much less demanding. By deliberately adopting such a conservative
- position, we lay ourselves open to the valid criticism that the methods
- described here will not prove necessary. Simpler techniques that relax
- to some degree the philosophical constraints we have imposed might well
- be adopted in practice. In this paper we will eschew the more exotic
- possibilities (without, however, adopting any position on their
- desirability).
-
- Another issue is not so much philosophical as emotional. Major surgery
- is not a pretty sight. There are few people who can watch a surgeon cut
- through living tissue with equanimity. In a heart transplant, for
- example, surgeons cut open the chest of a dying patient to rip out their
- dying heart, cut open a fresh cadaver to seize its still-beating heart,
- and then stitch the cadaver's heart into the dying patients chest.
- Despite this (which would have been condemned in the middle ages as the
- blackest of black magic), we cheer the patient's return to health and
- are thankful that we live in an era when medicine can save lives that
- were formerly lost.
-
- The mechanics of examining and repairing the human brain, possibly down
- to the level of individual molecules, might not be the best topic for
- after dinner conversation. While the details will vary depending on the
- specific method used, this could also be described by lurid language
- that failed to capture the central issue: the restoration to full
- health of a human being.
-
- A final issue that should be addressed is that of changes introduced by
- the process of restoration itself. The exact nature and extent of these
- changes will vary with the specific method. Current surgical
- techniques, for example, result in substantial tissue changes.
- Scarring, permanent implants, prosthetics, etc. are among the more
- benign outcomes. In general, methods based on a sophisticated ability
- to rearrange atomic structure should result in minimal undesired
- alterations to the tissue.
-
- "Minimal changes" does not mean "no changes." A modest amount of change
- in molecular structure, whatever technique is used, is both unavoidable
- and insignificant. The molecular structure of the human brain is in a
- constant state of change during life - molecules are synthesized,
- utilized, and catabolized in a continuous cycle. Cells continuously
- undergo slight changes in morphology. Cells also make small errors in
- building their own parts. For example, ribosomes make errors when they
- build proteins. About one amino acid in every 10,000 added to a growing
- polypeptide chain by a ribosome is incorrect[14, page 383]. Changes and
- errors of a similar magnitude introduced by the process of restoration
- can reasonably be neglected.
-
-
- Does the Information Theoretic Criterion Matter?
-
- It is normally a matter of small concern whether a physician of 2190
- would or would not concur with the diagnosis of "death" by a
- contemporary physician applied to a specific patient in 1990. A
- physician of today who found himself in 1790 would be able to do little
- for a patient whose heart had stopped, even though he knew
- intellectually that an intensive care unit would likely be able to save
- the patients life. Intensive care units were simply not available in
- 1790, no matter what the physician knew was possible. So, too, with the
- physician of today when informed that a physician 200 years hence could
- save the life of the patient that he has just pronounced "dead." There
- is nothing he can do, for he can only apply the technologies of today -
- except in the case of cryonic suspension.
-
- In this one instance, we must ask not whether the person is dead by
- today's (clearly technology dependent) criteria, but whether the person
- is dead by all future criteria. In short, we must ask whether death by
- the information theoretic criterion has taken place. If it has not,
- then cryonic suspension is a reasonable (and indeed life saving) course
- of action.
-
-
- Experimental Proof or Disproof of Cryonics
-
- It is often said that "cryonics is freezing the dead." It is more
- accurate to say that "cryonics is freezing the terminally ill. Whether
- or not they are dead remains to be seen."
-
- The scientifically correct experiment to verify that cryonics works (or
- demonstrate that it does not work) is quite easy to describe:
-
- 1.) Select N experimental subjects.
- 2.) Freeze them.
- 3.) Wait 200 years.
- 4.) See if the technology available 200 years from now can
- (or cannot) cure them.
-
- The drawback of this experimental protocol is obvious: we can't get the
- results for 200 years. This problem is fundamental. The use of future
- technology is an inherent part of cryonics.
-
- This kind of problem is not unique to cryonics. A new AIDS treatment
- might undergo clinical trials lasting a few years. The ethical dilemma
- posed by the terminally ill AIDS patient who might be assisted by the
- experimental treatment is well known. If the AIDS patient is given the
- treatement prior to completion of the clinical trials, it is possible
- that his situation could be made signficantly worse. On the other hand,
- to deny a potentially life saving treatment to someone who will soon die
- anyway is ethically untenable.
-
- In the case of cryonics this is not an interrim dilemma pending the
- (near term) outcome of clinical trials. It is a dilemma inherent in the
- nature of the proposal. Clinical trials, the bulwark of modern medical
- practice, are useless in resolving the effectiveness of cryonics in a
- timely fashion.
-
- Further, cryonics (virtually by definition) is a procedure used only
- when the patient has exhausted all other available options. In current
- practice the patient is suspended after legal death: the fear that the
- treatment might prove worse than the disease is absent. Of course,
- suspension of the terminally ill patient somewhat before legal death has
- significant advantages. For example, a patient suffering from a brain
- tumour might view suspension following the obliteration of his brain as
- significantly less desirable than suspension prior to such obliteration,
- even if the suspension occurred at a point in time when the patient was
- legally "alive."
-
- In such a case, it is inappropriate to disregard or override the
- patient's own wishes. To quote the American College of Physicians
- Ethics Manual, "Each patient is a free agent entitled to full
- explanation and full decision-making authority with regard to his
- medical care. John Stuart Mill expressed it as: 'Over himself, his own
- body and mind, the individual is sovereign.' The legal counterpart of
- patient autonomy is self-determination. Both principles deny legitimacy
- to paternalism by stating unequivocally that, in the last analysis, the
- patient determines what is right for him." "If the [terminally ill]
- patient is a mentally competent adult, he has the legal right to accept
- or refuse any form of treatment, and his wishes must be recognized and
- honored by his physician."[92]
-
- If clinical trials cannot provide us with an answer, are there any other
- methods of evaluating the proposal? Can we do more than say that (a)
- cryonic suspension can do no harm (in keeping with the Hippocratic
- oath), and (b) it has some difficult-to-define chance of doing good?
-
- Failure Criteria
-
- Trying to prove something false is often the simplest method of
- clarifying exactly what is required to make it true. A consideration of
- the information theoretic criterion of death makes it clear that, from a
- technical point of view (ignoring various non-technical issues) there
- are two and only two ways in which cryonics can fail[ft. 10].
-
- Cryonics will fail if:
-
- (1) Information theoretic death occurs prior to reaching liquid
- nitrogen temperature[ft. 11].
-
- (2) Repair technology that is feasible in principle is never developed
- and applied in practice, even after the passage of centuries.
-
- The first failure criterion can only be considered against the
- background of current understanding of freezing damage, ischemic injury
- and mechanisms of memory and synaptic plasticity. Whether or not memory
- and personality are destroyed in the information theoretic sense by
- freezing and the ischemic injury that might precede it can only be
- answered by considering both the physical nature of memory and the
- nature of the damage to which the brain is subjected before reaching the
- stability provided by storage in liquid nitrogen. The following
- sections will therefore provide brief reviews of these subjects.
-
- The second failure criterion is considered in the later sections on
- technical issues, which discuss in more detail how future technologies
- might be applied to the repair of frozen tissue.
-
- As the reader will readily appreciate, the following reviews will
- consider only the most salient points that are of the greatest
- importance in determining overall feasibility. They are necessarily too
- short to consider the topics in anything like full detail, but should
- provide sufficient information to give the reader an overview of the
- relevant issues. References to further reading are provided
- throughout[ft. 12].
-
-
- FREEZING DAMAGE
-
- There is an extensive literature on the damage caused by both cooling
- and freezing to liquid nitrogen temperatures. Some reviews are[5, 6,
- 68, 70]. Scientific American had a recent and quite accessible
- article[57]. In this section, we briefly review the nature of such
- damage and consider whether it is likely to cause information theoretic
- death. Damage, per se, is not meaningful except to the extent that it
- obscures or obliterates the nature of the original structure.
-
- While cooling tissue to around 0 degrees C creates a number of problems, the
- ability to cool mammals to this temperature or even slightly below (with
- no ice formation) using current methods followed by subsequent complete
- recovery[61, 62] shows that this problem can be controlled and is
- unlikely to cause information theoretic death. We will, therefore,
- ignore the problems caused by such cooling. This problem is discussed
- in [5] and elsewhere.
-
- Further, some "freezing" damage in fact occurs upon re-warming. Current
- work supports this idea because the precise method used to re-warm
- tissue can strongly affect the success or failure of present experiments
- even when freezing conditions are identical[5, 6]. If we presume that
- future repair methods avoid the step of re-warming the tissue prior to
- analysis and instead analyze the tissue directly in the frozen state
- then this source of damage will be eliminated. Several current methods
- can be used to distinguish between damage that occurs during freezing
- and damage that occurs while thawing. At present, it seems likely that
- some damage occurs during each process. While significant damage does
- occur during slow freezing, it does not induce structural changes which
- obliterate the cell.
-
- Present Day Successes
-
- Many types of tissue including human embryos, sperm, skin, bone, red and
- white blood cells, bone marrow, and others [5, 6, 59] have been frozen
- in liquid nitrogen, thawed, and have recovered. This is not true of
- whole mammals[ft. 13]. The brain seems more resistant than most organs
- to freezing damage[58, 79]. Recovery of overall brain function
- following freezing to liquid nitrogen temperature has not been
- demonstrated, although recovery of unit level electrical activity
- following freezing to -60 degrees C has been demonstrated[79].
-
- Fractures
-
- Perhaps the most dramatic injury caused by freezing is macroscopic
- fractures[56]. Tissue becomes extremely brittle at or below the "glass
- transition temperature" at about 140K. Continued cooling to 77K (the
- temperature of liquid nitrogen) creates tensile stress in the glassy
- material. This is exacerbated by the skull, which inhibits shrinkage of
- the cranial contents. This stress causes readily evident macroscopic
- fractures in the tissue.
-
- Fractures that occur below the glass transition temperature result in
- very little information loss. While dramatic, this damage is unlikely
- to cause or contribute to information theoretic death.
-
- Ice
-
- The damage most commonly associated with freezing is that caused by ice.
- Contrary to common belief, freezing does not cause cells to burst open
- like water pipes on a cold winter's day. Quite the contrary, ice
- formation takes place outside the cells in the extracellular region.
- This is largely due to the presence of extracellular nucleating agents
- on which ice can form, and the comparative absence of intracellular
- nucleating agents. Consequently the intracellular liquid supercools.
-
- Extracellular ice formation causes an increase in the concentration of
- the extra-cellular solute, e.g., the chemicals in the extracellular
- liquid are increased in concentration by the decrease in available
- water. The immediate effect of this increased extracellular
- concentration is to draw water out of the cells by osmosis. Thus,
- freezing dehydrates cells.
-
- Damage can be caused by the extracellular ice, by the increased
- concentration of solute, or by the reduced temperature itself. All
- three mechanisms can play a role under appropriate conditions.
-
- The damage caused by extracellular ice formation depends largely on the
- fraction of the initial liquid volume that is converted to ice[6, 57].
- (The initial liquid volume might include a significant amount of
- cryoprotectant as well as water). When the fraction of the liquid
- volume converted to ice is small, damage is often reversible even by
- current techniques. In many cases, conversion of significantly more
- than 40% of the liquid volume to ice is damaging[70, page 134; 71]. The
- brain is more resistant to such injury: conversion of up to 60% of the
- liquid volume in the brain to ice is associated with recovery of
- neuronal function[58, 62, 66, 82]. Storey and Storey said "If the cell
- volume falls below a critical minimum, then the bilayer of phospholipids
- in the membrane becomes so greatly compressed that its structure breaks
- down. Membrane transport functions cannot be maintained, and breaks in
- the membrane spill cell contents and provide a gate for ice to propagate
- into the cell. Most freeze-tolerant animals reach the critical minimum
- cell volume when about 65 percent of total body water is sequestered as
- ice."[57].
-
- Appropriate treatment with cryoprotectants (in particular glycerol)
- prior to freezing will keep more than 40% of the liquid volume from
- being converted to ice even at liquid nitrogen temperatures.
-
- Fahy has said "All of the postulated problems in cryobiology - cell
- packing [omitted reference], channel size constraints [omitted
- reference], optimal cooling rate differences for mixed cell populations
- [omitted reference], osmotically mediated injury[omitted references],
- and the rest - can be solved in principle by the selection of a
- sufficiently high concentration of cryoprotectant prior to freezing. In
- the extreme case, all ice formation could be suppressed completely by
- using a concentration of agent sufficient to ensure vitrification of the
- biological system in question [omitted reference]"[73]. Unfortunately,
- a concentration of cryoprotectant sufficiently high to protect the
- system from all freezing injury would itself be injurious[73]. It
- should be possible to trade the mechanical injury caused by ice
- formation for the biochemical injury caused by the cryoprotectant, which
- is probably advantageous. In some suspensions done by Alcor both venous
- and arterial glycerol concentrations have exceeded 6 molar. If this
- concentration of cryoprotectant is also reaching the tissues, it should
- keep over 60% of the initial liquid volume from being converted to ice
- at liquid nitrogen temperatures.
-
- Concentration Effects
-
- "Dehydration and concentration of solutes past some critical level may
- disrupt metabolism and denature cell proteins and macromolecular
- complexes"[70, page 125]. The functional losses caused by this
- mechanism seem unlikley to result in significant information loss. One
- qualification to this conclusion is that cell membranes appear to be
- weakened by increased solute concentration[5, page 92]. To the extent
- that structural elements are weakened by increased solute concentrations
- the vulnerability of the cell to structural damage is increased.
-
- Denaturing
-
- Finally, denaturing of proteins might occur at low temperature. In this
- process the tertiary and perhaps even secondary structure of the protein
- might be disrupted leading to significant loss of protein function.
- However, the primary structure of the protein (the linear sequence of
- amino acids) is still intact and so inference of the correct functional
- state of the protein is in principle trivial. Further, the extent of
- protein denaturation caused by freezing must necessarily be limited
- given the relatively wide range of tissues that have been successfully
- frozen and thawed.
-
- Intracellular Freezing
-
- Intracellular freezing is another damaging event which might occur[6].
- If cooling is slow enough to allow the removal of most of the water from
- the cell's interior by osmosis, then the high concentration of solute
- will prevent the small amount of remaining water from freezing. If
- cooling is too rapid, there will be insufficient time for the water
- within the cell to escape before it freezes. In the latter case, the
- intracellular contents are supercooled and freezing is abrupt (the cell
- "flashes"). While this correlates with a failure to recover function[5,
- 6, 68, 70] it is difficult to believe that flash freezing results in
- significant loss of information.
-
- Intracellular freezing is largely irrelevant to cryonic suspensions
- because of the slow freezing rates dictated by the large mass of tissue
- being frozen. Such freezing rates are too slow for intracellular
- freezing to occur except when membrane rupture allows extracellular ice
- to penetrate the intracellular region. If the membrane does fail, one
- would expect the interior of the cell to "flash."
-
- Loss of Information versus Loss of Function
-
- Spontaneous recovery of function following freezing to liquid nitrogen
- temperatures using the best currently available techniques appears
- unlikely for mammalian organs, including the brain. Despite this, the
- level of structural preservation can be excellent. The complexity of
- the systems that have been successfully frozen and rewarmed is
- remarkable, and supports the claim that good structural preservation is
- often achieved. While spontaneous recovery of function by the human
- brain cannot be viewed as likely, the mechanisms of damage that have
- been postulated in the literature are sufficiently subtle that
- information loss is likely to be small; that is, death by the
- information theoretic criterion is unlikely to have occurred.
-
-
- ISCHEMIC INJURY AND PRE-SUSPENSION INJURY
-
- Today, cryonic suspensions cannot be initiated until after legal death.
- Even operating under this constraint, it is often possible to initiate
- suspensions within two or three minutes following cessation of
- heartbeat. Future suspensions might eliminate delay entirely[ft. 14].
- However, delay is sometimes unavoidable[ft. 15]. The most significant
- type of damage that such delay causes is ischemic injury.
-
- It should be emphasized that delay in initiating cryonic suspension is
- caused by the current social and legal context. From a technical point
- of view it is usually relatively easy to initiate suspension without
- delay and without ischemia. It is therefore incorrect for two reasons
- to argue that cryonic suspension must fail because it is initiated
- following legal death. First, legal death and information theoretic
- death are logically distinct: information theoretic death will often
- occur well after legal death. Second, a change in legal climate would
- permit suspensions to begin prior to legal death. This would completely
- eliminate ischemia as a cause for concern in the feasibility of
- cryonics.
-
- Broadly speaking, the structure of the human brain remains intact for
- several hours or more following the cessation of blood flow, or
- ischemia. The tissue changes that occur subsequent to ischemia have
- been well studied. There have also been studies of the "postmortem"
- changes that occur in tissue. Perhaps the most interesting of these
- studies was conducted by Kalimo et. al.[65].
-
- "Postmortem" Changes in the Human Brain
-
- In order to study immediate "postmortem" changes, Kalimo et. al.
- perfused the brains of 5 patients with aldeyhydes within half an hour of
- "clinical death". Subsequent examination of the preserved brain tissue
- with both light and electron microscopy showed the level of structural
- preservation. In two cases, the changes described were consistent with
- approximately one to two hours of ischemic injury. (Ischemic injury
- often begins prior to declaration of "clinical death", hence the
- apparently longer ischemic period compared with the interval following
- declaration of death and prior to perfusion of fixative). Physical
- preservation of cellular structure and ultrastructure was excellent. It
- is difficult to avoid the conclusion that information loss was
- negligible in these cases. In two other cases, elevated
- intraparenchymal pressure prevented perfusion with the preservative,
- thus preventing examination of the tissue. Without such an examination,
- it is difficult to draw conclusions about the extent of information
- loss. In the final case, "...the most obvious abnormality was the
- replacement of approximately four-fifths of the parenchyma of the brain
- by a fluid-containing cavity that was lined by what seemed to be very
- thin remnants of the cerebral cortex." Cryonic suspension in this last
- case would not be productive.
-
- As an aside, the vascular perfusion of chemical fixatives to improve
- stability of tissue structures prior to perfusion with cryoprotectants
- and subsequent storage in liquid nitrogen would seem to offer
- significant advantages. The main issue that would require resolution
- prior to such use is the risk that fixation might obstruct circulation,
- thus impeding subsequent perfusion with cryoprotectants. Other than
- this risk, the use of chemical fixatives (such as aldehydes and in
- particular glutaraldehyde) would reliably improve structural
- preservation and would be effective at halting almost all deterioration
- within minutes of perfusion[67]. The utility of chemical preservation
- has been discussed by Drexler[1] and by Olson[90], among others.
-
- Ischemia
-
- The events following ischemia have been reasonably well characterized.
- Following experimental induction of ischemia in cats, Kalimo et. al.[74]
- found "The resulting cellular alterations were homogeneous and uniform
- throughout the entire brain: they included early chromatin clumping,
- gradally increasing electron lucency of the cell sap, distention of
- endoplasmic reticulum and Golgi cisternae, transient mitochondrial
- condensation followed by swelling and appearance of flocculent
- densities, and dispersion of ribosomal rosettes." Energy levels within
- the cell drop sharply within a few minutes of cessation of blood flow.
- The chromatin clumping is a reversible early change. The loss of energy
- results fairly quickly in failure to maintain trans-membrane
- concentration gradients (for example the Na+K+ pump stops working,
- resulting in increased intracellular Na+ and increased extracellular
- K+). The uneven equilibration of concentration gradients results in
- changes in osmotic pressure with consequent flows of water. Swelling of
- mitochondria and other structures occurs. The appearance of "flocculent
- densities" in the mitochondria is thought to indicate severe internal
- membrane damage which is "irreversible."[ft. 16]
-
- Ischemic changes do not appear to result in any damage that would
- prevent repair (e.g., changes that would result in significant loss of
- information about structure) for at least a few hours. Temporary and
- sometimes even permanent functional recovery has been demonstrated in
- optimal situations after as long as 60 minutes of total ischemia[93, 94,
- 95]. Hossmann, for example, reported results on 143 cats subjected to
- one hour of normothermic global brain ischemia[97]. "Body temperature
- was maintained at 36 to 37 degrees C with a heating pad. ... Completeness of
- ischemia was tested by injecting 133 Xe into the innominate artery
- immediately before vascular occlusion and monitoring the absence of
- decay of radioactivity from the head during ischemia, using external
- scintillation detectors. ... In 50% of the animals, even major
- spontaneous EEG activity returned after ischemia.... One cat survived
- for 1 yr after one hour of normothermic cerebrocirculatory arrest with
- no electrophysiologic deficit and with only minor neurologic and
- morphologic disturbances." Functional recovery is a more stringent
- criterion than the more relaxed information theoretic criterion, which
- merely requires adequate structural preservation to allow inference
- about the pre-existing structure. Reliable identification of the
- various cellular structures is possible hours (and sometimes even days)
- later. Detailed descriptions of ischemia and its time course[72, page
- 209 et sequitur] also clearly show that cooling substantially slows the
- rate of deterioration. Thus, even moderate cooling "postmortem" slows
- deterioration significantly.
-
- Lysosomes
-
- The theory that lysosomes ("suicide bags") rupture and release digestive
- enzymes into the cell that result in rapid deterioration of chemical
- structure appears to be incorrect. More broadly, there is a body of
- work suggesting that structural deterioration does not take place
- rapidly.
-
- Kalimo et. al.[74] said "It is noteworthy that after 120 min of complete
- blood deprivation we saw no evidence of membrane lysosomal breakdown, an
- observation which has also been reported in studies of in vitro lethal
- cell injury[omitted references], and in regional cerebral
- ischemia[omitted references]."
-
- Hawkins et. al.[75] said "...lysosomes did not rupture for approximately
- 4 hours and in fact did not release the fluorescent dye until after
- reaching the postmortem necrotic phase of injury. ... The original
- suicide bag mechanism of cell damage thus is apparently not operative in
- the systems studied. Lysosomes appear to be relatively stable
- organelles...."
-
- Messenger RNA and Protein
-
- Morrison and Griffin[76] said "We find that both rat and human
- cerebellar mRNAs are surprisingly stable under a variety of postmortem
- conditions and that biologically active, high-molecular-weight mRNAs can
- be isolated from postmortem tissue. ... A comparison of RNA recoveries
- from fresh rat cerebella and cerebella exposed to different postmortem
- treatments showed that 83% of the total cytoplasmic RNAs present
- immediately postmortem was recovered when rat cerebella were left at
- room temperature for 16 h [hours] postmortem and that 90% was recovered
- when the cerebella were left at 4 degrees C for this length of time .... In
- neither case was RNA recovery decreased by storing the cerebella in
- liquid nitrogen prior to analysis. ... Control studies on protein
- stability in postmortem rat cerebella show that the spectrum of abundant
- proteins is also unchanged after up to 16 h [hours] at room
- temperature...."
-
- 17 Million Year Survival of DNA
-
- The ability of DNA to survive for long periods was dramatically
- illustrated by its recovery and sequencing from a 17 to 20 million year
- old magnolia leaf[81]. "Sediments and fossils seem to have accumulated
- in an anoxic lake bottom environment; they have remained unoxidized and
- water-saturated to the present day." "Most leaves are preserved as
- compression fossils, commonly retaining intact cellular tissue with
- considerable ultrastructural preservation, including cell walls, leaf
- phytoliths, and intracellular organelles, as well as many organic
- constituents such as flavonoids and steroids[omitted references]. There
- is little evidence of post-depositional (diagenetic) change in many of
- the leaf fossils."
-
- Cell Cultures taken after "Death"
-
- Gilden et. al.[77] report that "...nearly two-thirds of all tissue
- acquired in less than six hours after death was succesfully grown,
- whereas only one-third of all tissue acquired more than six hours after
- death was successfully grown in tissue culture." While it would be
- incorrect to conclude that widespread cellular survival occurred based
- on these findings, they do show that structural deterioration is
- insufficient to disrupt function in at least some cells. This supports
- the idea that structural deterioration in many other cells should not be
- extensive.
-
- Information Loss and Ischemia
-
- It is currently possible to initiate cryonic suspension immediately
- after legal death. In favorable circumstances legal death can be
- declared upon cessation of heartbeat in an otherwise revivable
- terminally ill patient who wishes to die a natural death and has refused
- artificial means of prolonging the dieing process. In such cases, the
- ischemic interval can be short (two or three minutes). It is
- implausible that ischemic injury would cause information theoretic death
- in such a case.
-
- As the ischemic interval lengthens the level of damage increases. It is
- not clear exactly when information loss begins or when information
- theoretic death occurs. Present evidence supports but does not prove
- the hypothesis that information theoretic death does not occur for at
- least a few hours following the onset of ischemia. Quite possibly many
- hours of ischemia can be tolerated. Freezing of tissue within that time
- frame followed by long term storage in liquid nitrogen should provide
- adequate preservation of structure to allow repair[ft. 17].
-
-
- MEMORY
-
- It is essential to ask whether the important structural elements
- underlying "behavioral plasticity" (human memory and human personality)
- are likely to be preserved by cryonic suspension. Clearly, if human
- memory is stored in a physical form which is obliterated by freezing,
- then cryonic suspension won't work. In this section we briefly consider
- a few major aspects of what is known about long term memory and whether
- known or probable mechanisms are likely to be preserved by freezing.
-
- It appears likely that short term memory, which can be disrupted by
- trauma or a number of other processes, will not be preserved by cryonic
- suspension. Consolidation of short term memory into long term memory is
- a process that takes several hours. We will focus attention exclusively
- on long term memory, for this is far more stable. While the retention
- of short term memory cannot be excluded (particularly if chemical
- preservation is used to provide rapid initial fixation), its greater
- fragility renders this significantly less likely.
-
- To see the Mona Lisa or Niagara Falls changes us, as does seeing a
- favorite television show or reading a good book. These changes are both
- figurative and literal, and it is the literal (or neuroscientific)
- changes that we are interested in: what are the physical alterations
- that underlie memory?
-
- Briefly, the available evidence supports the idea that memory and
- personality are stored in identifiable physical changes in the nerve
- cells, and that alterations in the synapses between nerve cells play a
- critical role.
-
- Shepherd in "Neurobiology"[38, page 547] said: "The concept that brain
- functions are mediated by cell assemblies and neuronal circuits has
- become widely accepted, as will be obvious to the reader of this book,
- and most neurobiologists believe that plastic changes at synapses are
- the underlying mechanisms of learning and memory."
-
- Kupfermann in "Principles of Neural Science"[13, page 812] said:
- "Because of the enduring nature of memory, it seems reasonable to
- postulate that in some way the changes must be reflected in long-term
- alterations of the connections between neurons."
-
- Squire in "Memory and Brain"[109, page 10] said: "The most prevalent
- view has been that the specificity of stored information is determined
- by the location of synaptic changes in the nervous system and by the
- pattern of altered neuronal interactions that these changes produce.
- This idea is largely accepted at the present time, and will be explored
- further in this and succeeding chapters in the light of current
- evidence."
-
- Lynch, in "Synapses, Circuits, and the Beginnings of Memory"[34, page 3]
- said: "The question of which components of the neuron are responsible
- for storage is vital to attempts to develop generalized hypotheses about
- how the brain encodes and makes use of memory. Since individual neurons
- receive and generate thousands of connections and hence participate in
- what must be a vast array of potential circuits, most theorists have
- postulated a central role for synaptic modifications in memory storage."
-
- Turner and Greenough said "Two non-mutually exclusive possible
- mechanisms of brain information storage have remained the leading
- theories since their introduction by Ramon y Cajal [omitted reference]
- and Tanzi [omitted reference]. The first hypothesis is that new synapse
- formation, or selected synapse retention, yields altered brain circuitry
- which encodes new information. The second is that altered synaptic
- efficacy brings about similar change."[22].
-
- Greenough and Bailey in "The anatomy of a memory: convergence of results
- across a diversity of tests"[39] say: "More recently it has become
- clear that the arrangement of synaptic connections in the mature nervous
- system can undergo striking changes even during normal functioning. As
- the diversity of species and plastic processes subjected to
- morphological scrutiny has increased, convergence upon a set of
- structurally detectable phenomena has begun to emerge. Although several
- aspects of synaptic structure appear to change with experience, the most
- consistent potential substrate for memory storage during behavioral
- modification is an alteration in the number and/or pattern of synaptic
- connections."
-
- It seems likely, therefore, that human memory is encoded by detectable
- physical changes in cell structure and in particular in synaptic
- structure.
-
- Plastic Changes in Model Systems
-
- What, exactly, might these changes be? Very strong statements are
- possible in simple "model systems". Bailey and Chen, for example,
- identified several specific changes in synaptic structure that encoded
- learned memories from sea slugs (Aplysia californica) by direct
- examination of the changed synapse with an electron microscope[36].
-
- "Using horseradish peroxidase (HRP) to label the presynaptic terminals
- (varicosities) of sensory neurons and serial reconstruction to analyze
- synaptic contacts, we compared the fine structure of identified sensory
- neuron synapses in control and behaviorally modified animals. Our
- results indicate that learning can modulate long-term synaptic
- effectiveness by altering the number, size, and vesical complement of
- synaptic active zones."
-
- Examination by transmission electron microscopy in vacuum of sections
- 100 nanometers (several hundred atomic diameters) thick recovers little
- or no chemical information. Lateral resolution is at best a few
- nanometers (tens of atomic diamters), and depth information (within the
- 100 nanometer section) is entirely lost. Specimen preparation included
- removal and desheathing of the abdominal ganglion which was then bathed
- in seawater for 30 minutes before impalement and intrasomatic pressure
- injection of HRP. Two hours later the ganglia were fixed,
- histochemically processed, and embedded. Following this treatment,
- Bailey and Chen concluded that "...clear structural changes accompany
- behavioral modification, and those changes can be detected at the level
- of identified synapses that are critically involved in learning."
-
- The following observations about this work seem in order. First,
- several different types of changes were present. This provides
- redundant evidence of synaptic alteration. Inability to detect one type
- of change, or obliteration of one specific type of change, would not be
- sufficient to prevent recovery of the "state" of the synapse. Second,
- examination by electron microscopy is much cruder than the techniques
- considered here which literally propose to analyze every molecule in the
- structure. Further alterations in synaptic chemistry will be detectable
- when the synapse is examined in more detail at the molecular level.
- Third, there is no reason to believe that freezing would obliterate the
- structure beyond recognition.
-
- Implications for Human Memory
-
- Such satisfying evidence is at present confined to "model systems;" what
- can we conclude about more complex systems, e.g., humans? Certainly, it
- seems safe to say that synaptic alterations are also used in the human
- memory system, that synaptic changes of various types take place when
- the synapse "remembers" something, that the changes involve alterations
- in at least many thousands of molecules and probably involve mechanisms
- similar to those used in lower organisms (evolution is notoriously
- conservative).
-
- It seems likely that knowledge of the morphology and connectivity of
- nerve cells along with some specific knowledge of the biochemical state
- of the cells and synapses would be sufficient to determine memory and
- personality. Perhaps, however, some fundamentally different mechanism
- is present in humans? Even if this were to prove true, any such system
- would be sharply constrained by the available evidence. It would have
- to persist over the lifetime of a human being, and thus would have to be
- quite stable. It would have to tolerate the natural conditions
- encountered by humans and the experimental conditions to which primates
- have been subjected without loss of memory and personality (presuming
- that the primate brain is similar to the human brain). And finally, it
- would almost certainly involve changes in tens of thousands of molecules
- to store each bit of information. Functional studies of human long term
- memory suggest it has a capacity of only 10^9 bits (somewhat over 100
- megabytes)[37] (though this did not consider motor memory, e.g., the
- information storage required when learning to ride a bicycle). Such a
- low memory capacity suggests that, independent of the specific
- mechanism, a great many molecules are required to remember each bit. It
- even suggests that many synapses are used to store each bit (recall
- there are perhaps 10^15 synapses - which implies some 10^6 synapses per
- bit of information stored in long term memory).
-
- Given that future technology will allow the molecule-by-molecule
- analysis of the structures that store memory, and given that such
- structures are large on the molecular scale (involving tens of thousands
- of molecules each) then it appears unlikely that such structures will
- survive the lifetime of the individual only to be obliterated beyond
- recognition by freezing. Freezing is unlikely to cause information
- theoretic death.
-
-
-